Some excerpts from: Altering Baby Boys' Bodies: The Ethics of Infant Male Circumcision, Margaret A. Somerville
A common error made by those who want to justify infant male circumcision on the basis of medical benefits is that they believe that as long as some such benefits are present, circumcision can be justified as therapeutic, in the sense of preventive health care. This is not correct. A medical-benefits or therapeutic
justification requires that overall the medical benefits sought outweigh the risks and harms of the procedure required to obtain them, that this procedure is the only reasonable way to obtain these benefits, and that these benefits are necessary to the well-being of the child. None of these conditions is fulfilled for routine infant male circumcision. If we view a child's foreskin as having a valid function, we are no more justified in amputating it than any other part of the child's body unless the operation is medically required treatment and the least harmful way to provide that treatment.
~ (pp. 204-205.)
It is very difficult to believe that a person, especially a physician, could understand the new knowledge about circumcision and believe that it did little or no harm to the baby boys on whom it is carried out. And yet my experience has been that many physicians, especially those who are older and have performed very large numbers of circumcisions, are unwilling to accept this evidence or, it seems, even to give it open-minded consideration. In by far the majority of cases, this resistance is not connected with physicians' own religious beliefs, although it could, of course, be connected with concern that recognizing the harms involved in infant male circumcision could interfere with others' religious beliefs or traditional or cultural practices. This concern probably influences politicians and leaders of medical professional societies. When approached about the ethics and legality of infant male circumcision, they frequently fail to respond. If they do respond, either they state that the practice does not raise any ethical or legal issues or, if they recognize that it does raise these issues, they often justify the practice with statements that are ethically and legally wrong. I have spent many hours replying to letters signed by ministers of justice or of health, or presidents of colleges of physicians and surgeons. In these letters, I give the same arguments that I discuss in this chapter to explain why, in my opinion, they are ethically and legally wrong. Sometimes, I do not receive any reply, but I have found that when I do receive a response, it rarely addresses the ethical and legal issues I have raised and often simply repeats the same statements as those in the letter to which I replied that I argued were wrong. I assume that these statements are made in good faith. Probably the people making them are acting out of a concern not to distress their constituents or members of the colleges who would be deeply dismayed by recognizing the harms involved in infant male circumcision that are not compensated for by medical benefits, and therefore the practice's ethical and legal unacceptability. No doubt they are also dismayed to realize that as parents who consented to routine circumcision, they may have inflicted harm on their sons or, as physicians who carried it out, on other people's sons.
~ (pp. 206-207)
The assault provisions in the current [Canadian] Criminal Code could be used to stop infant male circumcision, but this route is probably neither the most ethical nor the most effective way to approach a situation that involves long-standing, deeply held social, cultural and religious beliefs. In particular, we have to start from a basis of deep respect for religious belief and a requirement of very strong justification for any interference with the expression of this belief.
~ (pp. 209-210)
Under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms---as is true under most codes of human rights---discrimination on the basis of sex is prohibited. Legislatures must not pass laws that protect people of one sex but not the other when both are in similar situations. People who oppose infant male circumcision argue that the provision in the Canadian Criminal Code that specifically prohibits genital mutilation only on females is discriminatory in that it protects the right to security of the person
of girls but not of boys and that this failure to protect boys is unconstitutional. In all likelihood, we will see this issue addressed by the courts in the not too distant future, probably in the context of a man suing a physician on the grounds that in circumcising him as a child, a legal wrong was done to him, and that governmental action, in either formulating or applying the law in such a way that he was not protected, was unconstitutional.
~ (pp. 210-211)
Physicians who undertake infant male circumcision could be legally liable for medical malpractice (civil liability in battery or negligence), which can result in an award of damages simply for carrying out the circumcision even if it was competently performed. They could also, as explained, be charged with criminal liability for assault. In both ethics and law, a physician has a primary obligation of personal care to the patient. This obligation requires the physician both to place the patient first and to first do no harm. Physicians who undertake surgery on patients must prove that it is justified. The usual justification is that the surgery is necessary therapy and that the patient---or if incompetent, the patient's legal representative---gave informed consent to the surgery. In general, parents cannot authorize non-therapeutic interventions---that is, routine circumcision---on their children. A competent adult man could consent to non-therapeutic circumcision on himself, but this does not mean he may consent to it on his son. If the parents' consent to the circumcision of their son was held to be legally inoperative, the physician would be liable. Moreover, if, in the light of new medical evidence, a reasonably careful and competent physician would not consider it medically necessary to undertake circumcision on a child, to do so could result in legal liability regardless of the parents' consent. Such liability is even more likely if a reasonably careful and competent physician would consider it not just unnecessary but contrary to a reasonable standard of medical care to undertake circumcision on a particular child in given circumstances. A long-recongnized example of such a situation is when the child suffers from haemophilia, a condition that could cause him to bleed to death from circumcision. But as our knowledge of the risks and harms of circumcision expands, the range of circumstances in which undertaking routine circumcision on any child is a breach of a reasonable standard of medical care also expands. To summarize, it seems to me clear that, certainly outside the religious context, recent medical research on routine infant male circumcision shows that this operation cannot be ethically or legally justified on the basis of its potential medical benefits.
~ (pp. 211-212)
There has been some confusion about the ethical and legal effect of this lack of a medical justification for routine infant male circumcision, particularly on the part of medical associations who seem to be concerned not to speak out against the practice. For instance, the American Academy of Pediatrics recognizes that the potential medical benefits of this procedure do not outweigh its risks to a degree that it can be recommended to parents as a routine procedure. But they then conclude that the decision about circumcision should be left to the parents in consultation with their physician. In my opinion, this conclusion is wrong both ethically and legally. Unless the potential and actual medical benefits of a surgical intervention on a child unable to consent for himself clearly outweigh its risks (and the academy has found that in the case of routine infant male circumcision they do not), then it cannot be ethically or legally justified just on the basis of the parents' consent and, therefore, the physician must not undertake it unless he or she has some other justification for doing so. The question therefore is how should we balance respect for baby boys' rights to physical integrity and parents' responsibilities and rights with regard to their children and to their freedom of conscience and religion?
~ (pp. 212-213)
The Ethical Canary: Science, Society and the Human Spirit
by Margaret Somerville.
Toronto, 2000: Viking (published by the Penguin Group)
ISBN 0-670-89302-1
Hardcover 344 pages
$Can 33.99
Available online from Canada's largest book retailer: http://www.chapters.ca/ (Sale price: Can$23.79, about US$16)
Note:
The Circumcision Information and Resource Pages are a not-for-profit educational resource and library. IntactiWiki hosts this website but is not responsible for the content of this site. CIRP makes documents available without charge, for informational purposes only. The contents of this site are not intended to replace the professional medical or legal advice of a licensed practitioner.
© CIRP.org 1996-2024 | Filetree | Please visit our sponsor and host: IntactiWiki.